Historiographic
Metafiction, Or Lying with the Truth
The
disciplines of history and literature have, like many other fields
of critical inquiry, since the advent of Saussurian and Peircian
semiotics, been re-evaluating the premises of their enterprise.
The threadbare ‘truth’ offered by linguistics, that language,
the basis of our only knowable reality, is founded upon an arbitrary
and essentially meaningless relationship between the signifier
and the signified, has caused both fields to examine anew the
textual coding that historical and literary texts employ.
Writing
after one of the momentous historical events of our century, the
apocalyptic years of World War I, the philosopher/historian R.
G. Collingwood roots his genealogical study of historiography
in the ancient debate between Herodotus (who is interested more
in a history of events) and Thucydides (who analysed the laws
which order these events) in an attempt to describe a development
of historiography. Following the evolution of historical writing
(by use of an unproblematized progress narrative), Collingwood’s
study traces historiography from the multiple narrative of Herodotus
to Livy, to the Renaissance and Enlightenment historiographers,
and the “single history” of Hegel and Marx (123). Collingwood
does not merely catalogue the change in the philosophical underpinnings
of historiography, however. Instead of merely working within what
he condescendingly defines as a “common-sense theory” of historiography,
he challenges and problematizes the premises of each historiographical
system (234). Collingwood begins an investigation of history’s
problematic faith in its own veracity by citing examples such
as Kant’s claim that history uses “the language of metaphor,”
and Wilhelm Dilthey’s question of “how the historian actually
performs the work of coming to know the past, starting as he does
simply from documents and data which do not by themselves reveal
it” (95 and 172). Far from offering such pleasing narratives as
Benedetto Croce’s dictum of art, which paraphrases Aristotle,
“art in general, in the wide sense, represents or narrates the
possible; history represents or narrates that which really happened,”
Collingwood compares the similarities of historians and the novelist
(192):
Each of
them makes it his [her] business to construct a picture which
is partly a narrative of events, partly a description of situations,
exhibition of motives, analysis of characters. Each aims at
making his [her] picture a coherent whole, where every character
and every situation is so bound up with the rest that this character
in this situation cannot but act this way, and we cannot imagine
him [her] as acting otherwise. The novel and the history must
make sense; nothing is admissible in either except what is necessary
and the judge of this necessity is in both cases the imagination.
Both the novel and history are self-explanatory, self-justifying,
the product of an autonomous or self-authorizing activity; and
in both cases this activity is the a priori imagination.
(245-6)
This
way of understanding history (similar to the thrust of Hayden
White’s notion of narrativization many years later) stresses the
importance of what Collingwood calls the constructive imagination
(which he sees as a Kantian a priori structure) which orders
the otherwise random facts that make up historical events. As
Nietzsche suggests, “there are no facts in themselves, for a fact
to exists, we must first introduce meaning” (in Barthes “Historical
Discourse” 153). By use of “interpolation,” Collingwood argues,
the historian, like Iser’s reader, “concretizes” the gaps between
historical events and thus makes the narrative “without which
we would have no history at all” (241).
It
is worthwhile here to follow the implications that Iser’s model
has for Collingwood’s notion of the constructive imagination.
For the reader/historian to fully actualize the historical text,
this ‘concretization’ must eliminate textual ‘indeterminacy’ and
permit the consistency building which is essential for meaning-making.
The reader/historian does this by filling in gaps, occupying vacancies,
connecting segments, and negating the given according to instructions
encoded textually which can be culturally agreed upon. Textual
indeterminancies spur the historian to abolish them, to ‘normalize’
them into some firm structure of sense. Iser’s reader seeks to
reduce the polysemic quality of the text by basing the intentional
object’s simulation (which we may think of as the historical text)
upon the ‘determinantness’ of ‘real’ objects. Collingwood does
not carry his understanding of the historian’s process of narrativization
to Iser's logical conclusion. He does allow, however, what he
calls the “critical historian” to tamper, presumably in a responsible
fashion, with facts in that s/he selects what s/he thinks are
important and to omit what does not add to narrative understanding
or what they read as being due to “misinformation” (245).
Before
he is drawn into making even more daring statements about historical
truth however, Collingwood lapses into an implicit positive empiricist
faith that facts are knowable. His historian organizes, for the
sake of comprehension, the facts in accordance to well known and
understandable narratives. The similarity of the historian’s action
to the manipulation of detail by the novelist is inescapable,
however:
Where they
do differ is that the historian’s picture is meant to be true.
The novelist has a single task only: to construct a coherent
picture, one that makes sense. The historian has a double task:
he has both to do this, and to construct a picture of things
as they really were and of events as they really happened. (245-6).
Collingwood’s
distinction between the novelist and the historian is one that
later theorists would not make. He claims that in this procedure
of “scissors and paste,” the historian must take into account
evidence or detail about which the novelist does not have to worry
(281). For Collingwood's historian picks and chooses from
the evidence, or the contingencies of events, in order to incorporate
those elements which make the most sense in terms of his/her project.
So both historian and novelist are subject to the demands of narrative,
Collingwood would argue, but the historian must write coherent
narrative around unavoidable historical details while the novelist
is subject to the demands of narrative only. He further shores
up this narrative hole in scientific history’s defence by presenting
three rules which guide the historian’s craft and to which, he
would claim, the novelist is not subject. The historian’s image
of the past “must be localized in space and time,” “history must
be consistent with itself” and “the historian’s picture stands
in a peculiar relation to something called evidence” (246). Collingwood’s
novelist, presumably, is subject to nothing except the roving
of his/her constructive imagination.
While
Collingwood’s analysis might seem to end up in an excessively
simplistic comprehension of history and narrative, his three rules
are a useful summary of traditional historiographical expectations
against and within which historiographic metafiction works. For
example, the obsession that Elsa Morante's History, a Novel
has with dates and historical fact foregrounds how little traditional
or official history tells of the bulk of history’s story (a bulk
foregrounded for the reader by the time spent following the travails
of one family during the war). Likewise, history’s inability to
be consistent with even its own report is foregrounded by both
Thomas Pynchon’s The Crying of Lot 49 and John Fowles'
A Maggot. Both texts posit a problematic investigative
narrator who uncovers endless discourse instead of an eventual
truth. Collingwood’s “peculiar” relationship between the historiographical
text and evidence is similarly flaunted by Daphne Marlatt’s Ana
Historic in which Ana’s recovery from the forgetful chauvinistic
historical record is almost total. Ana Historic foregrounds
the minimal presence of women in official record in order to work
against history's ideologically created silence. Citing the brief
entrance of a woman into Vancouver's public record, Marlatt writes
history's unsaid: "by 1873 she is there, named in the pages
of history as 'Mrs. Richards, a young and pretty widow' who fills
the suddenly vacated post of school teacher" (21). Deliberately
foregrounding Mrs. Richards' lack of name, as well as definitions
of self by other, Marlatt's text does not attempt to mine official
documents in order to construct a past, but rather reveals the
absence which is woman in traditional historiography by self-consciously
creating both name and life for this unsung woman. Postmodern
historiographic metafiction works within, by either tacitly accepting
or self-reflexively undermining, these historiographical conventions
in order to foreground the constructed nature of the conventions
themselves as ontological objects of inquiry.
In
“Narrative Form as a Cognitive Instrument” Louis Mink picks up
on Collingwood’s comparison between fiction and history. He argues
that narrative is “a primary and irreducible form of human comprehension”
used by history as a transparent entity to organize historical
truth (186). He claims that common-sense historiography, like
that which Collingwood’s defines, works out of presuppositions
from Universal History which presume that history relates an actual
story. Mink questions the naturalized nature of these presuppositions
by asking, and here he quotes Kant, how we discover, in the plethora
of detail, “a single central subject or theme in the unfolding
of the plot of history” (190). He asks how it is, in both fiction
and history, that narrative detects the ‘evidence’ in its selection
of events. Taking this analysis one step further, Mink also questions
the seeming consensus which defines the historical event (this
is similar to Nietzsche’s questioning of facts). He suggests that
narrative organizes its selection of events, and that an event
is an abstraction from narrative. Mink contrasts the faith of
an objective history that presupposes “that past actuality is
an untold story and that there is a right way to tell it,” with
the “conceptual discomfort” history experiences when it encounters
alternative versions (a discomfort history ignores by its facile
categorization of subjective and objective truth) (196). This
discomfort, he assures us, is not shared by fiction. Although
Mink’s more esoteric questioning of historical events and Hegelian
themes are not themselves useful to this study, his general arguments
do build upon Collingwood’s discussion by further defining the
narrative basis of historical truth and by problematizing the
machinery behind the selection of evidence. They point to a more
global questioning of history which is not undermined by an attachment
to positive empiricism.
Hayden
White’s examination of history similarly questions the epistemological
status of historical knowledge and the role of narrative in historical
presentation. He argues that “history remains in the state of
conceptual anarchy,” that narrative is a meta-code which informs
both fiction and historiography, and that the historical text
shares many of its codes with the literary artifact (Metahistory
13). Citing Lévi-Strauss, White agrees with arguments like
Mink’s by positing “the centrality of narrativity to the production
of cultural life in all its forms” (“Question” 112). He claims
that historians select and organize historical information in
specific patterns in order to make their rendering more understandable
to “an audience of a particular kind” and insists that the idea
that you have found coherence in the historical record implies
a belief in a desire for a kind of formal coherence. (Metahistory,
5). By ignoring the performative nature of narrative, traditional
historiography leaves out the basis of what transforms mere chronicle
to narrative historiography:
. . . in
this process of literalization, what gets left out is precisely
those elements of figuration, tropes and figures of thought,
as the rhetoricians call them, without which the narrativization
of real events, the transformation of chronicle into a story,
could never be effected. . . . To leave this figurative element
out of consideration in the analysis of a narrative is not only
to miss its aspect as allegory; it is also to miss the performance
in language by which a chronicle is transformed in a narrative.
(“Question” 125)
Historians
find data, organize, and construct it along the narrative lines
of what White calls emplotment: “Providing the ‘meaning’ of a
story by identifying the kind of story that has been told
is called explanation by emplotment” (Metahistory 7):
Histories
. . . combine a certain amount of “data,” theoretical concepts
for “explaining” these data, and a narrative structure for their
presentation as an icon of sets of events presumed to have occurred
in times past. In addition, I maintain, they contain a deep
structural content which is generally poetic, and specifically
linguistic, in nature, and which serves as the precritically
accepted paradigm of what a distinctively “historical” explanation
should be. (Metahistory ix)
White
uses Northrop Frye’s four archetypal categories of plot to argue
that history is cast in particular literary modes. This “essentially
poetic act” is one in which the historian “prefigures
the historical field and constitutes it as a domain upon which
he will bring to bear the specific theories he will use to explain
‘what was really happening’ in it” (Metahistory x).
In White’s Romance, the hero overcomes his/her world, in his Satire,
we are victims of the fates, Comedy allows its characters a temporary
triumph and Tragedy allows the audience to gain consciousness.
Both the novelist and the historian share this emplotment of subject
matter, its strategies of exclusion, and demand for emphasis.
The plausibility of history, says White, is dependent not on the
coherence of the facts so ordered, but on the historian’s skill
in matching up a set plot structure with a series of facts.
Both
for history and fiction, facts are constituted by the questions
we ask and are carved up and selected always by a manifest or
latent motive or aim (Tropics 43). White would disagree
with the freedom that Collingwood allows his a priori “constructive
imagination”. He would instead argue that this imagination is
bound and ordered in accordance to the rules of narrative, as
well as is subject to the subjectivity of the particular historian
and the “irreducible ideological component in every historical
account of reality” (Metahistory 21).
Michel
Foucault, whose paradigm has politicized and historicized the
notions of the discursive text in such provocative and politically
meaningful ways, also describes the ideological power of language
and knowledge in society: “Foucault is seen as providing a call
to or model for historical and political criticism that would
relate texts to historically-defined forces” (Culler, Framing
62). Foucault’s methodology, by refusing to accept traditional
distinctions between literature and non-literature, subverts notions
of literature’s distinctive qualities by calling for a literary
criticism which is aware of both history and literature’s provisional
and changing character. Foucault’s heavily problematized notion
of an author function, as a guarantor of meaning, can only work
(that is make meaning) within societal conventions: “. . . he
[she] can only write poetry, or history, or criticism only within
the context of a system of enabling conventions which constitute
and delimit the varieties of discourse” (Ibid. 30).
Foucault’s
claims that social institutions construct themselves through these
types of discursive practices, building the rules and systems
that make possible certain structures and significations, and
thus enable certain types of knowledge. Utilizing a concept of
the ‘episteme,’ the epistemological paradigm governing what it
is that is considered truth or knowledge at a time, this methodology
argues both from “the assumption that reality is socially constructed,”
and that a combination of discourses, assumptions and values distinguish
historical power (Wuthnow 133). Foucault’s “Excerpts from The
History of Sexuality: Volume I: An Introduction” envisions power
as a site, upon which numerous discourses (not through reasoned
action but rather a strategical sense) sort through a fluctuating
dynamic equilibrium of power relations. Different forms of discourse
are regulated by an array of institutional constraints, and the
links between power and knowledge characterize the ‘disciplinary’
character of all modern political organizations and institutional
practices. Institutions such as Law join in the production of
knowledge of a particular field to exercise power in society as
a whole. As social relationships change, however, power constantly
renews itself through the discourse of truth:
There can
be no possible exercise of power without a certain economy of
discourses of truth which operates through and on the basis
of this association. We are subjected to the production of truth
through power and we cannot exercise power except through the
production of truth. (Foucault, History of Sexuality
93)
The
notion of hierarchical power has little to do with Foucault’s
model. This is a network of relationships which ties ruler and
ruled together, for there is no exterior of power. Operating in
a vast web of specific conflicts, power regulates the language
and comprehension of the speaker’s self. Foucault’s genealogical
interpretation examines how we place our subjectivity in relation
to knowledge and how we place the power relations of our subjectivity
in relation to the general field of power (through which we constitute
ourselves). This placement of the text and subject in history
is not in any sense a conventional understanding of history, however:
Foucault
performs the same renversement in relation to the accepted
modes of historical analysis: those which describe history in
terms of continuities, like tradition, influence or the genetic
origin and development of phenomena, and those which describe
it in terms of continuous teleologies like evolution or the
progress of man [humanity] towards some future golden age; those
which give history an anthropological subject, describing it
in terms of human intentionality . . . Foucault [treats] history
as a series of specific and concrete but changing events which
occur by chance and exist with their own interrelationships.
(Bannet 102)
This
theoretical stance approaches history by foregrounding the way
in which both the production and consumption of the historical
text shows it to be a writing practice constituted within a restrictive
discourse.
The
implications this linguistic analysis of power has for the subject
in history are far-ranging. In an examination of the prison system,
for example, the conceptualization of power in “Discipline and
Punish” reaches past the limits of law and repression to actually
produce the individual as a subject in, as well as subject to,
the disciplinary mechanisms of the state. Problematizing notions
of individual specificity and unity, and positioning him/her in
language as “reduced . . . to a grammatical function,” Foucault’s
paradigm
demonstrates
how . . . man himself [humanity] becomes an irrationality in
a special sense, a structure that dramatizes the normally unthinkable
relationship between the diversities of knowledge. No longer
a coherent cogito, man [humanity] now inhabits the interstices,
“the vacant interstellar spaces,” not as an object, still less
as a subject; rather man [humanity] is the structure,
or the generality of relationships between those words and ideas
we call the human . . . (Said, “ABECEDARIUM” 350, 348)
By
positioning the subject within the interstices of text (an argument
which inevitably foregrounds the socially valorized discourse
of historical text), Foucault’s notion of historical power is
much more extreme than White’s. Foucault directly combats White’s
vague statements concerning ideological constructions of the state
by investigating this conjunction of textual historical truth
with power. Foucault’s concepts not only empower historical truth
but point out the ways in which discourses such as historiographic
metafiction overturn that truth. Read through Foucault’s theorizing,
historiographic metafiction is the minor literature (in Guattari
and Deleuze’s terms) or the “unsaid” of historical practice, which
works to subvert dominant historiographical assumptions and practice.
For example, momentarily ignoring the more humorous Foucauldian
implications a graduate dissertation implies, a Foucauldian reading
of this project would problematize the narrative of influence
my argument, for the sake of a White-type coherence, creates.
Using militaristic terms like “combat” and “overturns,” my argument
attempts to assert its truth value by reference to extant historiographical
codes which valorize a narrative of progression.
This
cursory examination of the historiography’s changing climate in
regard to the knotty question of historical veracity, positions
the argument that informs the postmodern historical novel. Working
out of a wish to reexamine and, in some cases, rationalize, the
truth practice of their enterprise, modern historians (although
much more concerned with what literary technique, such as what
narrative offers historical practice) have offered many valuable
notions to literary theorists’ investigation of fictional historical
texts. Although the focus of these historians was principally
to question the specific strategies narrative offers history,
the type of narrative history’s rhetorical stances imply, and
how narrative not only delivers but constructs meaning, their
theories were picked up by literary theorists with an entirely
different agenda.
|